Tagged: Féminisme

LV The Island of Dr Bentham

Quelques passages bibliques cités par Swedenborg dans ses Arcana Cœlestia, en l’occurrence dans le cahier relatif à 1 Mos. 1-3 (édition suédoise, qui n’est pas l’édition originale en latin). Mon objet n’est pas de rendre compte ici de l’interprétation ésotérique que Swedenborg donne de ces passages ; je me borne à demander à mon lecteur si de tels passages, tellement bizarres, peuvent admettre autre chose qu’une interprétation ésotérique (quand bien même on l’appellerait symbolique ou allégorique) pour quelqu’un qui croit à la sainteté des Écritures.

Pour montrer, peut-être, la perplexité des traducteurs devant ces passages, je donne pour chacun deux traductions françaises, celle de la Bible de Jérusalem (BJ) (catholique) et celle de Louis Segond (LS) (suisse protestante), comme je l’ai déjà fait en d’autres occasions, ici (voyez en commentaires) et ici.

Isaïe 46:11

« J’appelle depuis l’Orient un rapace, d’un pays lointain l’homme que j’ai prédestiné. » BJ

« C’est moi qui appelle de l’orient un oiseau de proie, D’une terre lointaine un homme pour accomplir mes desseins. » LS

Pourquoi cet homme prédestiné est-il appelé rapace ou oiseau de proie ?

Osée 2:20

« Je conclurai pour eux une alliance, en ce jour-là, avec les bêtes des champs, avec les oiseaux du ciel et les reptiles du sol » BJ

« En ce jour-là, je traiterai pour eux une alliance avec les bêtes des champs, les oiseaux du ciel et les reptiles de la terre » LS

Admettons que ce passage soit à prendre littéralement : qui a dit que les animaux n’avaient pas d’âme, puisque Dieu conclut une alliance avec eux ? Sinon, de quoi ces animaux sont-ils la métaphore ?

Job 5:23

« Car tu feras alliance avec les pierres des champs » BJ

« Tu auras un pacte avec les pierres des champs » LS

Isaïe 43:20

« Les bêtes sauvages m’honoreront » BJ

« Les bêtes des champs me glorifieront » LS

Isaïe 43:7 (c’est Dieu qui parle)

« Tous ceux qui se réclament de mon nom » (BJ)

« Tous ceux qui s’appellent de mon nom » (LS)

Ici, BJ interprète le sens littéral pour écrire quelque chose de compréhensible. LS garde le sens littéral et n’est guère compréhensible tel quel. (Le texte suédois est conforme à la traduction de LS : « Envhar, som är kallad med mitt Namn… ».)

Ézéchiel 31:18

« Pourtant tu fus précipité avec les arbres d’Eden vers le pays souterrain, au milieu des incirconcis » BJ

« Tu sera précipité avec les arbres d’Éden Dans les profondeurs de la terre, Tu seras couché au milieu des incirconcis » LS

Pourquoi cette punition des arbres d’Eden, qui l’ont méritée au même titre que les incirconcis ?

(Notez au passage la différence de temps entre les deux traductions : dans un cas un souvenir, dans l’autre une menace.)

Vasarely (Beaubourg 2019)

*

Louis XVI : « On ne gouverne pas un pays contre l’esprit dominant. »

Bien vu.

*

« Si le soleil est caché par les nuages, il ne change pas de place pour autant, ni ne perd sa merveilleuse splendeur. » (Miguel de Molinos, Guide spirituel, 1675)

La même image, la même belle pensée se retrouve, identique, sous la plume de Gandhi.

*

« Jésus-Christ n’a pas voulu choisir des gens savants et habiles pour la prédication de l’Évangile et pour la conversion du monde, mais seulement de pauvres pêcheurs et des gens simples et grossiers, qui n’eussent aucune science. » (R. P. Rodriguez, Pratique de la perfection chrétienne, 1615)

Il choisit des « pauvres pêcheurs » qui furent capables d’écrire des évangiles en grec, qui ne devait pas être leur langue maternelle.

Or puisque les apôtres sont les auteurs des évangiles, ils étaient savants : c’est la conclusion de Daniel-Rops, dans L’Église des apôtres, ouvrage qui a reçu l’imprimatur de l’Église.

En résumé, pour l’Église, les apôtres étaient de pauvres pêcheurs savants…

D’ailleurs, elle ne sait plus si les quatre apôtres sont les auteurs des évangiles qui portent leurs noms.

*

« Il haïssait cette franc-maçonnerie de pissotières » (Sartre, L’âge de raison)

Cette même « franc-maçonnerie » est appelée, toujours par Sartre, « la franc-maçonnerie des pauvres », dans Le sursis.

*

« Je viens de lire sur le transparent d’un journal anglais : Ruhr Coal peace hope. Mettez l’ordre inverse, propre au français ; vous auriez : espoir pacifique charbonnier ruhrien. Eh bien ! non, non et non ! le français pense : espoir de pacification dans les mines de la Ruhr. Votre emploi d’épithètes juxtaposées ne tend à rien de moins qu’à supprimer l’analyse rationnelle des idées ! … Les constructions agglomérées et madréporiques répugnent au génie analytique et dissociateur (pour ainsi parler) de notre langage. » (Jacques Boulenger et André Thérive, Les soirées du Grammaire-Club, 1924)

Voyez le début d’analyse que je fais de l’anglais comme « langue topologique » chez Arnold Gehlen (ici) : chez ce dernier, ce n’est pas un défaut.

La traduction « espoir de pacification dans les mines de la Ruhr » laisse d’ailleurs coal de côté, et il faudrait en fait, pour rendre fidèlement la construction « madréporique » anglaise, écrire, en suivant le modèle indiqué : espoir de pacification dans les mines de charbon de la Ruhr, autrement dit, traduire quatre mots par onze, ce qui est presque trois fois plus long !

Le principe d’économie n’est pas mauvais en soi. Je me rappelle combien j’étais frappé, dans le métro de Boston, Massachusetts, de voir que les traductions espagnoles des consignes en anglais (car le bilinguisme tendait alors à se généraliser dans cette ville) étaient beaucoup plus longues que l’original ; et je me faisais la réflexion qu’une telle apparence n’était pas de nature à rendre l’espagnol attrayant. Pourquoi un anglophone voudrait-il apprendre une langue s’il perçoit, dans le métro, qu’elle nécessite une bien plus grande prolixité pour parvenir au même résultat, la consigne étant forcément la même dans l’une et l’autre langues ?

Or, en examinant ces consignes, je constatai que le traducteur espagnol en disait d’une certaine façon plus que l’original, par exemple en parlant de « poignée de porte » là où l’original anglais se contente d’indiquer la « poignée », et tout le reste à l’avenant. Cette minutie sans doute bien intentionnée ne peut que rendre l’espagnol peu attrayant pour ceux qui ne le parlent pas, ne peut que conforter les anglophones dans le sentiment intime de la supériorité de leur langue, comparée à une langue en apparence si prolixe. Ces traductions donnent le sentiment que l’espagnol est une langue qui fait perdre son temps à celui qui la parle, car il pourrait dire, et par conséquent penser deux fois plus de choses dans la journée en parlant anglais.

Je soumets cette réflexion aux traducteurs de profession, surtout pour ces messages fonctionnels ou commerciaux comme on en trouve dans le métro : rendez votre langue économique !

D’ailleurs, Boulenger et Thérive donnent, dans leur roman, le nom très madréporique de Grammaire-Club à leur société d’amis de la langue française, et non celui de Club de Grammaire ou Club des Grammairiens. Et club est un mot anglais.

*

« Les fous ont toujours été et seront toujours le plus grand nombre. » (Diderot, Entretien d’un philosophe avec la Maréchale de…)

Peut-on être démocrate avec une telle conviction ?

*

« René Leibovitz … joua au piano de la musique dodécaphonique ; je n’y compris rien ; mais elle avait été interdite par les nazis. » (Simone de Beauvoir, La force des choses)

*

« On dit que plusieurs sages-femmes prétendent, en pétrissant la tête des enfants nouveau-nés, lui donner une forme plus convenable, et on le souffre ! » (Rousseau, Émile)

Les déformations crâniennes pratiquées par les Huns, les Incas, et d’autres, poursuivaient-elles un objectif physiognomonique, à savoir le développement des facultés intellectuelles dans une certaine direction ?

*

« Les enfants sont si longtemps rampants et faibles, que la mère et eux se passeraient difficilement de l’attachement du père, et des soins qui en sont l’effet. » &

« L’homme est sociable par sa nature, ou du moins fait pour le devenir. » (Rousseau, Émile)

Que l’on songe au prodige de subtilité dans l’idée que l’homme est par nature fait pour devenir sociable, plutôt que sociable par nature. Rousseau ne pouvait tout simplement pas ne pas ajouter « ou du moins fait pour le devenir », sans jeter à terre son état de nature et son Contrat social. Je voudrais toutefois que les penseurs qui discutent de son contrat social et de son état de nature, gardent présents à l’esprit les deux citations ci-dessus.

*

« La liberté n’est dans aucune forme de gouvernement. » (Rousseau, Émile)

Une pensée de l’auteur du Contrat social.

*

Die Träume für bloßes Gedankenspiel, bloße Phantasiebilder ausgeben zu wollen zeugt von Mangel an Besinnung oder an Redlichkeit. … Diesem Satze vom Grunde als den ausnahmslosen Prinzip der Abhängigkeit und Bedingtheit aller irgend für uns vorhandenen Gegenstände müssen nun auch die Träume hinsichtlich ihres Eintritts irgendwie unterworfen sein: allein auf welche Weise sie ihm unterliegen, ist sehr schwer auszumachen. (Schopenhauer, Versuch über das Geistersehn und was damit zusammenhängt)

L’influence de Schopenhauer sur Freud est plus ou moins connue des biographes de ce dernier. La citation ci-dessus contient en germe la théorie freudienne des rêves, dans la mesure où l’on y trouve l’expression d’une pertinence du contenu des rêves autrement que dans le contexte irrationnel de l’oniromancie de la plus haute antiquité.

En examinant ensuite les propositions de l’oniromancie antique, qu’il décrit comme fondée sur une clé d’interprétation en quelque sorte universelle du symbolisme des rêves, indépendante des individus, Schopenhauer s’en écarte en affirmant que l’interprétation est à produire à partir de la biographie individuelle, ce qui est purement et simplement une première expression, à ma connaissance, du postulat de la théorie psychanalytique des rêves :

Allein diese [Oniromantik des Artemidoros u.a.] fügt die Voraussetzung hinzu, daß die Vorgänge im Traum eine feststehende, ein für allemal geltende Bedeutung hätten, über welche sich daher ein Lexicon machen ließe. Solches ist aber nicht der Fall: vielmehr ist die Allegorie dem jedesmaligen Objekt und Subjekt des dem allegorischen Traume zum Grunde liegenden theorematischen Traumes eigens und individuell angepaßt. (Ibid.)

Sur cette base, Freud se mit à chercher de quelle manière les événements de la vie individuelle se traduisent en symboles oniriques.

*

Die Batrachier führen vor unsern Augen ein Fischleben, ehe sie ihre eigene, vollkommenere Gestalt annehmen, und nach einer jetzt ziemlich allgemein anerkannten Bemerkung durchgeht ebenso jeder Fötus sukzessive die Formen der unter seiner Spezies stehenden Klassen, bis er zur eigenen gelangt. Warum sollte nun nicht jede neue und höhere Art dadurch entstanden sein, daß diese Steigerung der Fötusform einmal noch über die Form der ihn tragenden Mutter um eine Stufe hinausgegangen ist? (Schopenhauer, Parerga und Paralipomena)

C’est  la « loi biogénétique » du darwinien Haeckel : l’ontogenèse récapitule la phylogenèse.

Les textes de Parerga et Paralipomena ont été publiés en 1851, L’origine des espèces de Darwin en 1859, et la loi biogénétique de Haeckel a été rendue publique en 1866 !

Il est également significatif que « la remarque selon laquelle le développement de chaque fœtus adopte successivement les formes des classes existantes de son espèce jusqu’à parvenir à la sienne propre », la loi biogénétique, donc, soit appelée par Schopenhauer « une observation à présent reconnue de façon assez générale ».

Même s’il peut paraître un peu vague, ce passage de Schopenhauer ne permet pas de douter qu’il s’agit d’évolution des espèces : les différentes « classes » d’espèces sont pensées comme inscrites dans un processus temporel d’évolution, de l’ancien et « inférieur » au nouveau et « supérieur » (« jede neue und höhere Art »).

Que l’évolution soit linéaire de cette façon, le darwinisme a montré, bien que de nombreux darwiniens aient maintenu cette façon de voir, que c’était vrai en tendance, sous l’effet de la sélection naturelle, mais que les circonstances pouvaient tout aussi bien conduire à des « régressions », et qu’il convenait au fond d’abandonner un vocabulaire à connotation hiérarchique en ces matières, car des « régressions » sont adaptatives.

Je renvoie le lecteur à mon « Schopenhauer père de Darwin » (x). L’histoire de la théorie de l’évolution a été falsifiée par de pseudo-intellectuels chauvinistes. Le darwinisme est apparu dans un milieu scientifique saturé d’observations et d’hypothèses relatives à l’évolution des espèces, dont l’espèce humaine ; il a contribué à unifier l’ensemble de ces observations et hypothèses dans une théorie générale cohérente, mais il n’est guère permis de dire que ce fut une révolution dans les esprits, car de nombreux autres esprits que Darwin cherchaient ce que ce dernier a finalement trouvé.

*

« Être sujet aux lois, c’est être sujet de l’État, c’est-à-dire du représentant souverain, c’est-à-dire de soi-même : ce qui n’est pas de la sujétion, mais de la liberté. » (Hobbes, Léviathan)

Cette définition de la loi et de l’autonomie du citoyen soumis aux lois sera reprise par Rousseau, puis par Kant.

*

Selon Hobbes, l’âme en tant que substance incorporelle n’est pas une notion chrétienne mais païenne.

« Que l’âme de l’homme soit, dans sa propre nature, éternelle, et une créature vivante indépendante du corps, ou que n’importe quel homme soit immortel, autrement que par la résurrection du dernier jour, c’est une doctrine qu’on ne trouve pas dans l’Écriture. » (Hobbes, Léviathan)

« Dans l’Écriture, l’âme signifie toujours ou bien la vie ou bien la créature vivante … Dieu créa les baleines, et omnem animam viventem [etc] … Si, en s’appuyant sur ces passages, le mot âme signifie une substance incorporelle, qui existe indépendamment du corps, on pourrait aussi bien déduire la même chose de n’importe quelle créature vivante » (Ibid.)

« Les humains … étaient en général possédés, avant la venue de notre Sauveur, par suite de la contagion de la démonologie des Grecs, par cette opinion selon laquelle les âmes des humains sont des substances distinctes de leurs corps. » (Ibid.)

*

En lieu et place de philosophie, Hobbes affirme que les théologiens scolastiques pratiquent l’aristotélité (cf. Léviathan). Schopenhauer a fait le même constat avec les philosophes d’université, qui pratiquent la Hegelei.

Schopenhauer reste à ce jour le mal-aimé des études philosophiques universitaires. Son âme peut se consoler en pensant à l’influence que son œuvre a exercée sur des écrivains et penseurs de la plus haute importance. (Puisque j’ai parlé plus haut de son influence sur Freud, qu’il me soit permis de préciser que Freud n’est pas inclus selon moi parmi ces penseurs de la plus haute importance.)

*

« Un arbre isolé dans la campagne pousse de travers, il étend largement ses branches ; en revanche, un arbre qui se dresse en pleine forêt pousse droit parce que les arbres voisins lui résistent, il cherche l’air et le soleil au-dessus de lui. » (Kant, Propos de pédagogie)

(On le trouve également dans les manuscrits non publiés de Kant (Nachlaß 1499) : ,,Bäume nötigen sich einander, gerade zu wachsen.’’)

Image que l’on retrouve à l’identique, sans le nom de Kant, dans Citadelle de Saint-Exupéry :

« Mais les arbres que j’ai vus jaillir le plus droit ne sont point ceux qui poussent libres. Car ceux-là ne se pressent point de grandir, flânent dans leur ascension et montent tout tordus. Tandis que celui-là de la forêt vierge, pressé d’ennemis qui lui volent sa part de soleil, escalade le ciel d’un jet vertical, avec l’urgence d’un appel. »

*

« Le sexe masculin, quoique le plus fort, n’a pas fait la loi à son avantage, en établissant les ménages isolés et le mariage permanent qui en est une suite. » (Charles Fourier)

Aussi ne l’a-t-il établi que parce que les femmes ont mis à ce prix la jouissance sexuelle (Schopenhauer).

Les théories féministes, si l’on veut, qui prétendent que les ménages isolés, monogames et plus ou moins indissolubles seraient une caractéristique patriarcale, sont loin du compte ; c’est un théoricien de la liberté sexuelle, Fourier, qui le dit.

Selon des études plus récentes, le ratio des sexes dans une société donnée (qui fluctue autour de 1:1) détermine le degré de promiscuité : plus les femmes sont nombreuses, plus la promiscuité est grande car, l’homme étant alors relativement rare, ce sont ses exigences qui font loi.

En quoi le mariage, avant notre supposée émancipation des femmes (plutôt que des hommes), était défavorable au mari, le même Fourier l’a amplement démontré :

« Les dogmes religieux, plus sévères que dans l’antiquité, interdisent au mari certaines précautions que dicte la prudence : Interdictio semen effusendi extra vas debitum (Interdiction de répandre la semence en dehors du vase vaginal). La femme l’exige par masque de piété ; son vrai motif est de légitimer les œuvres d’un amant. » &

« Cocu de par la loi est celui dont la femme fait un enfant de contrebande évidente, comme un mulâtre, quarteron ou octavon. La tricherie est incontestable ; mais les formes ont été observées, et la loi adjuge au mari cet enfant … Selon le beau principe : Is pater est quem nuptiae demonstrant (N’est père que celui dont le mariage a prouvé qu’il l’est). »

Et voilà un exemple de ce que ça donne, quand un de ces grands esprits dont j’ai parlé plus haut a lu Schopenhauer, comme l’écrivain et poète Thomas Hardy : « It appears that ordinary men take wives because possession is not possible without marriage, and that ordinary women accept husbands because marriage is not possible without possession; with totally different aims the method is the same on both sides. » (Hardy, Far from the madding crowd)

*

So long as visible or audible pain turns you sick, so long as your own pains drives you, so long as pain underlies your propositions about sin, so long, I tell you, you are an animal, thinking a little less obscurely what an animal feels. &

This store men and women set on pleasure and pain, Prendick, is the mark of the beast upon them, the mark of the beast from which they came. (H.G. Wells, The Island of Dr Moreau)

So much for Bentham and other ‘Utilitarians’ (from the mad scientist who’s a genius in his own right).

*

Modern torturers in Chile break down prisoners by putting them in cells where everything –walls, furniture, ustensils, window covers– is painted white. (Marshall McLuhan & Bruce Power, The Global Village, 1989)

Un peu comme nos hôpitaux publics, en somme. On n’est pourtant pas censés s’y faire torturer (les opérations se passent sous anesthésie). S’agit-il de dissuader d’y entrer, une opération plus ou moins inconsciente de maîtrise des coûts ?

*

Psychoanalysts are fascinating as a special sort of clowns. They have the same attraction as circus freaks, or of distorting mirrors. They evoke the court dwarves of gone ages, whose charm, if one may say, lied in their making themselves funny either by endorsing something elevated or by finding it defective in some way or other.

*

Everyone wants to be a star, who cares about privacy?

*

L’ordre moral a, dit-on, été explosé par les nécessités de la consommation de masse, qui doit saborder parcimonie, frugalité, tempérance, mais la répression des pulsions sexuelles implique bien d’autres ressorts que la pénurie de biens matériels, pour qu’elle ait disparu avec cette pénurie.

*

Selon John C. Lilly, l’intelligence à l’état solide (solid state intelligence, SSI), c’est-à-dire l’intelligence artificielle devenue autonome, doit détruire l’humanité, à composante principalement aqueuse (water-based), car les conditions environnementales de sa survie impliquent la suppression de l’air humide, de l’eau.

Ce n’est pas sans angoisse qu’il décrit un tel scénario, et qu’il cherche les moyens de le prévenir, mais il ne démontre pas que notre instinct de survie s’étend à la survie de l’espèce humaine en tant que telle. En réalité, c’est ce qu’il est impossible de démontrer : l’instinct de survie est un instinct exclusiviste. Mes gènes veulent prédominer contre d’autres gènes au sein de l’espèce, ils ne savent pas ce qu’est une menace d’extinction de l’espèce.

Si je raisonne sur une telle extinction, je ne raisonne déjà plus au niveau génétique, et la justice implique donc de peser le pour et le contre entre la SSI et nous sur un plan autre que génétique.

*

Les gens mentent. Ils donnent aux marketeurs les réponses qui, leur semble-t-il, les font paraître intelligents et distingués. Ils mentent sur leurs préférences, leurs habitudes (nient avoir emprunté de l’argent, mentent sur ce qu’ils lisent), leurs motivations… C’est pourquoi les marketeurs ont dû mettre au point des approches qui ne reposent plus seulement sur des questionnaires adressés à des échantillons de consommateurs. Avis aux chercheurs français en sciences sociales.

*

Les lois de la nature nous apportent, dit Berkeley, la régularité et la prévisibilité qui rendent nos activités possibles. Mais c’est bien par ces mêmes lois que se produit un jour la catastrophe naturelle inattendue qui prend tout le monde de court, comme si personne ne connaissait les lois de la nature. Elles ne sont donc pas une preuve de sagesse ou de bonté divine, elles ne nous donnent qu’une sécurité trompeuse. Toute notre science est un bluff.

*

C’est une curieuse conception de considérer que le droit à l’anonymat est une composante critique du débat public, alors que c’est la preuve que les individus ne sont pas libres de s’exprimer.

Je défends en effet l’idée que nul ne doit être inquiété pour ses paroles.

*

C’est quand même dégueulasse : sous la monarchie, les femmes n’avaient pas le droit de vote.

*

Plus on va haut, plus l’air est raréfié et plus il est difficile de se maintenir longtemps à la même altitude : « travail inégal ».

*

Freedom-free zone.

*

No freedom from freedom for the enemies of freedom from freedom.

*

C’est sa mère qui l’a marié. Peut-être même qu’elle lui tenait la main lors de sa nuit de noces.

*

Dans l’édition de Matérialisme et empiriocriticisme, par Lénine, qui se trouve dans ma bibliothèque, dans l’index Engels a le droit, j’ai compté, à dix-sept lignes de références, tandis que Marx a le droit à treize. On parle de marxisme parce que c’est plus simple qu’« engelsisme ».

*

When all is said and done, poetry wins.

XXIX The Science of Sex II

Dr Robin Baker’s Science of Sex II

In his reply to my essay on what I called his Sex Wars trilogy (Dr Robin Baker’s Science of Sex: A Discussion, XXVIII, here), Robin Baker pointed out three blunders I made, and for the rest invited me to read the book he authored with Mark Bellis, Human Sperm Competition. Copulation, Masturbation and Infidelity (1995), which presents the results of their research in a more systematic and detailed fashion. I then ordered the book and read it. The present essay is intended as a sequel to XXVIII; it acknowledges that my non-specialist objections on particular points of Baker’s theory have found satisfactory answers in Human Sperm Competition, and further expatiates on a few inferences I draw from the theory.

human_sperm_competition

As a sequel, the present essay perhaps should not be read before taking cognizance of the content of the original essay (here). A brief introduction on human sperm competition can also be found here (XXVII).

The abbreviations for the book titles have been maintained from the former essay. Further on Human Sperm Competition will be found abbreviated as HSC. I am using the first hardback edition by Chapman & Hall, 1995.

Before I tell how my objections and doubts have been satisfied, one word on the blunders Baker pointed out in his reply (a reply I have posted as a comment to XXVIII). They are three: one on method, two on content.

On the method, I had made some quotes from the collective work Sperm Competition in Humans (SCH) without naming the authors of the passages quoted. I have since then corrected the slip in the text itself, acknowledging the fact in a further comment.

Another blunder I made, this time regarding the content of Baker’s books, was that I construed the expression ‘clear eyes’ as meaning ‘fair eyes’. Hence my questions on this point lacked an actual ground, because they were based on a semantic misunderstanding. Baker made it clear in his reply.

The second blunder on content concerns some figures on the extent of human sperm competition. Baker answered with an extensive quote from HSC showing that my remarks, here again, were groundless. I shall deal with this point more at length, explaining the nature of my blunder, under the head “Conception Via Sperm Warfare: The Figures.”

I shall now proceed with exposing how my objections have been answered, under the same heads, or subtitles, used in XXVIII.

Female Orgasm

Under this head I did not exactly make an objection; it was rather a request for more information. I requested, namely, a confirmation that via copulatory orgasm, as an operation by which the outcome of sperm competition can be slanted, women really manage to discriminate between sperm from different men, and how. I think I now understand the mechanism better.

As I understand things, female copulatory orgasms discriminate between different sperm as long as these are not mixed in one and the same seminal pool. It means that copulatory orgasms are of no avail when two successive copulations by two different men occur before a flowback (expulsion of sperm from the female’s genital tract) has resulted from the first insemination. Quoth: “The overall pattern is more or less as predicted by the ‘upsuck’ hypothesis, female orgasm in some way assisting uptake of sperm from the seminal pool before the remainder of the sperm are ejected in the flowback.” (HSC, 236, box 10.5). & “Orgasm facilitates the passage of sperm from the seminal pool to the cervical mucus. It could do this in one or all of several ways: (1) dipping the cervix further into the seminal pool; (2) promoting greater mixing of cervical mucus and seminal fluid; (3) lengthening and/or increasing the number of seminal projections into the cervical mucus; and/or (4) lengthening the time that the cervix is dipped in the seminal pool.” (HSC, p. 237). Thus, the mechanism of female copulatory orgasm in any case exerts itself on a given seminal pool, and would not be able to discriminate among the content of that pool if composed of various sperm.

As a result, the example I took in XXVII of an orgy is an instance where a woman would be least likely to slant the result of insemination, if male participants inseminate her by turns without interruption, because orgasm upsuck would then apply to a multifarious seminal pool in which the favorite male’s semen is mixed with other males’ sperm. Admittedly, such configuration is relatively rare (even in the context of an orgy, flowbacks may occur between several inseminations, if the participants make breaks; quoth: “Median time to emergence of the flowback after male ejaculation is 30 minutes with a range of 5-120 min” [HSC, 45]) and copulatory orgasms remain useful in the majority of cases of sperm competition, the woman favoring the sperm contained in a homogeneous seminal pool although she may at the moment of orgasm shelter sperm from another insemination in her cervical crypts and/or oviducts (these latter sperm being not impacted by orgasm).

If this is so, it raises a question: What sperm does the penis, in its function of sperm-removal tool, actually remove? Is it only ‘flowback sperm’, so-called, forming a seminal pool in the upper vagina and due to be ejected very soon? Quoth: “Backward and forward thrusting of the penis during copulation, combined with the shape of the penis in a distended vagina should successfully remove a major part of any soft copulatory plug or liquid seminal pool.” (HSC, 171). It thus seems that the answer to the question is yes. However, “The greater the suction, the greater the chance of removing cervical mucus with perhaps older sperm from the cervix itself.” (HSC, 170, box 6.13). I stressed the word ‘perhaps’ because it makes a big difference whether the penis can remove sperm already stored in the cervix or not; for if it cannot, it then applies to present seminal pools merely, that is, in the context present-day customs, it never serves most of times. In the absence of a seminal pool, if we keep assuming that the penis can’t remove sperm stored in the cervix, it can still remove sperm, but it is flushed-out sperm mixed with leucocytes that invalidate them and cells and debris from the female (HSC, 40, box 3.5), that is, sperm unlikely to perform fecundation anyway – sperm that is being removed by the female tract itself (after flowback), without the help of a ‘piston penis’.

As we saw from quote HSC, 45, in general flowbacks occur fairly quickly after intercourse. The probability that another intercourse occurs before flowback should in normal circumstances be deemed small as a consequence, and if ‘flowback sperm’ merely is exposed to the action of the piston penis, it makes the latter’s usefulness rather low. This way open to men to slant sperm competition seems fairly inadequate, whereas the corresponding way open to women, their copulatory orgasms, is effective in most cases and can be foiled by very specific contrivances only (above mentioned), which anyway imply a degree of sperm competition.

The picture I have just outlined, based on my understanding of the facts, is that of a radical asymmetry between women and men in regard of their respective physiological endowments for slanting sperm competition. HSC has provided me with a confirmation that female copulatory orgasm can discriminate among different sperm, in the limits above presented, and with the insight that the limits of the piston penis’ usefulness are important. Of course, we should not disregard the fact that Baker & Bellis consider that the penis can ‘perhaps’ remove sperm from the cervix as well, but they give no clue as to how that would happen.

Oral Sex

My objection, under this head, was that the passive gender in an act of oral sex (men in the case of fellatio, women in that of cunnilingus) should have evolved a dislike for the practice, and that, not only have they not, but according to a study by Eysenck et al. it is the active gender that generally expresses a dislike (men say they dislike cunnilingus, women say they dislike fellatio). As Baker, in his trilogy, presents oral sex as a way to collect information (on health and faithfulness), I could have replied to my own objection myself: since it is about exchange of information, if one partner is eager to get information the other may as well be willing to provide it. Which is what Baker & Bellis say: “The main feature of overt orgasms is that the climaxing individual is giving their partner information. … If the transference of this range of information is sufficiently advantageous to both male and female, it could be enough evolutionarily to maintain the observed behaviour. The main topic of theoretical interest then becomes the optimum ratio of cryptic to overt orgasms for male and female performers and observers.” (HSC, 115).

For the man, giving information is a straightforward transparency operation, but Baker & Bellis hint at another set of motivations for the woman: “As far as the climaxing female is concerned, the interplay of cryptic and overt orgasms is a major part of her strategy to confuse the male over levels of sperm retention. Allowing the male to observe a non-copulatory orgasm could be an important element in this strategy.” (HSC, 115).

As to Eysenck et al.’s study, the fact that primates and other mammals practice oral sex (HSC, 101) may cast some doubt on the validity of its results. Otherwise, it could be that the dislike is true generally and that oral sex is performed because of its strategic importance albeit not accompanied by pleasure, but such a view would run contrary to the notion that evolutionary useful acts are predicted to be pleasurable to their performers.

Ejaculates

Under the present head, I expressed some doubt on the likelihood of an energetic trade-off model, based on the testes’ huge sperm productivity. It turns out the trade-off considered by Baker is not necessarily that which I thought of: “Such restraint over the number of sperm ejaculated when the risk of sperm competition is low implies that males suffer some disadvantage if they ejaculate too many sperm on any given occasion. Two main disadvantages have been suggested: (1) that the sperm and other constituents in an ejaculate are costly to produce (Dewsbury, 1982); and (2) that, in the absence of sperm competition, the more sperm a male ejaculates, the lower his chances of fertilizing the egg(s) of the current female (Baker & Bellis, 1993).” (HSC, 24). So, the idea of an energetic trade-off is credited to Dewsbury, whereas Baker & Bellis, quoting their own research, hint at another phenomenon, namely that too many sperm may act as a chemical weapon against the woman’s eggs.

My objection taking sperm productivity into account (for the figures, see XXVIII) could still hold against Dewsbury’s model, but it is limited to sperm and I have nothing to say about the productivity of ‘other constituents’ of an ejaculate, i.e. the seminal fluid, which may be much more costly to produce and spend than sperm themselves.

Baker & Bellis do not formally reject Dewsbury’s model and in at least one occasion they seem, on the contrary, to rely on it: “The disadvantage of small testes should be that their possessors produce fewer sperm per day and thus, all else being equal, must either: (1) ejaculate less often and, on average, inseminate older sperm; or (2) ejaculate as often and, on average, inseminate fewer sperm.” (HSC, 111). Such calculations are based on a cost analysis of sperm production and seem to imply the validity of Dewsbury’s energetic trade-off as regard sperm themselves.

Furthermore, the idea that sperm competition itself has being selecting big testes for their capacity to produce more sperm and thus give their owner an advantage in sperm competition, fits the energetic model. There is, seemingly, no way to escape the model, no matter how the figures of sperm production make the very idea of a trade-off along energetic lines puzzling.

Accordingly, Baker & Bellis’s careful conclusion is not surprising: “At present, we cannot determine the relative importance of this factor [optimizing sperm numbers according to levels of sperm competition] and any constraint on sperm numbers due to the cost of producing ejaculates (Dewsbury, 1982). Inevitably, ejaculate cost must have been a factor in the evolution of species-specific rates of sperm production. It is possible, however, that at least for mammals ejaculate cost could be less important than the factors discussed here in influencing restraint over the number of sperm inseminated on any given occasion.” (HSC, 227).

Conception Via Sperm Warfare: The Figures

Baker has replied to my remarks under this head by quoting extensively the relevant passage from HSC (see his reply in comment on XXVIII). To put in a nutshell, I had lost sight of one important possibility, which Baker & Bellis put thus forth: “a female may be paired to one male, conceive by another (via infidelity, and perhaps sperm competition)” (HSC, 200, box 8.4). When writing that part of my essay, I fancied that no woman would conceive via infidelity without sperm competition, because I overlooked the possibility of breakdowns in routine sex. Given that “On average, human pairs engage in IPC [intrapair copulation] at median intervals of about every three days” (HSC, 206), and that Baker & Bellis retain a life expectancy of sperm inside the female tract of 5 days (they present this figure as a conservative estimate), in the normal course of events no female infidelity goes without sperm competition. But one must not rule out the possibility that some men may be crazy enough to neglect routine sex with their long-term partner, or that ‘accidents’ can occur, and that a woman might cheat her partner when he has been lying on a hospital bed for weeks. Because of that blunder of mine, the discussion of the figures in XXVIII is meaningless.

With this head, the discussion of the strictly biological aspects of Baker’s writings is through. I have acknowledged my mistakes as far as I could detect them, and I now proceed to some social considerations, where I find my opinions are more solid.

Pornography

HSC does not deal with pornography as such. However, some passages confirm my point of view as to how the phenomenon should be construed. As previously stressed, Baker has evolved from the idea that Western societies are becoming increasingly puritanical to the more optimistic view that the current ‘generation porn’ represent an emancipated and enlightened brand of humanity. My own view is that neither picture is correct, but rather that there is a risk that we become increasingly incapacitated sexually. Puritanism has sometimes been construed as a way to cope with sexual inadequacies, but as an ideal of strict monogamy, it cannot, except in marginal cases, be interpreted as such, and Puritans of the past are known among other things for their philoprogenitiveness.

From the evidence of SF 279-80, I have stressed that prostitution in the West has been declining. (Although he provides the figures on which I rely, Baker himself does not construe them in this way; he just offers them as evidence of prostitution in the USA and UK.) In the past, particularly when brothels were legal and widespread, many a young man would have his first sexual experience with a prostitute (of which scores of novels attest, as well as sociohistoric literature). These data make one conclusion pretty tempting, I should think, and HSC buttresses it: “Inexperienced male monkeys and chimpanzees, when encountering a receptive female, become strongly sexually aroused but are often so awkward at attempting intromission that the mating is never completed. Adults who have been denied the opportunity to gain sexual experience when younger are often unable to copulate (Ford and Beach, 1952). A level of experience with other males would be of obvious advantage in increasing the success of an individual’s first mating opportunitites with a female. There may well be some advantage in using other males as targets for practice rather than females. Females, because of the risk of conception, may less often than males be prepared to allow males the opportunity to experiment.” (HSC, 118). Needless to say, Baker & Bellis generalize the findings to humans. In a nutshell, they credit homosexual practice with the same ‘educative’ virtues evidenced by prostitution in the past.

So, if it is true that prostitution has declined (and let the reader be reminded of recent legal developments in some countries such as France, where paying for the services of a prostitute has been criminalized; this criminalizing occurring at a time when prostitution has already sharply declined, law-makers cannot contain the lyrical flows of their eloquence against such a barbarous exploitation of women, failing to see, or rather feigning not to see the far more impressive figures of pornography), if, I say, prostitution has declined, and homosexuality has not increased in due proportion, of which I am not aware (and Baker says it remains stable), certainly one should expect that more men stay virgins for want of experience at the right time.

Do contemporary mores compensate for that? At least two elements should induce us to doubt it. First, feminism has been a strong deterrent to male urgency, as well as the most recent forms of democratism: the vanishing of an utterly dependent servile class has narrowed opportunities for well-off young men to inseminate female servants with the certainty of avoiding unpleasant consequences. Some stories by a Maupassant, for instance, cannot but be met with incredulity nowadays, although they may be more realistic in the context of his time. Second, the mediatic buzz about AIDS, now receding, has certainly played a deterrent role. I have shown elsewhere (here, in French) that the treatment of this sexually transmitted disease by the French media in the nineties was disproportionate. I have shown that, at the apex of the AIDS razzmatazz, an heterosexual individual was 55 times more likely to die in a car accident, and 10 times more likely to die assassinated; and that drugs-addicts were far more likely to contract AIDS via intravenous injection by contaminated syringes (one out of 25 drugs-addicts was then expected to die from AIDS) than gays via sexual intercourse! The buzz must have had a powerful deterrent effect, especially since the only known way to prevent AIDS apart from abstinence, the condom, could never be deemed 100% safe. On this last point, I reminded my reader of the failure rates generally acknowledged, but HSC brings forth even higher figures: “condoms retain a high chance of fertilization. Although, when used properly, the risk of conception with a condom may be as low as three pregnancies per 100 woman years, in normal usage the risk varies from 5 to 30 pregnancies per 100 woman years. This is up to about half the risk experienced by a fertile couple with no protection.” (HSC 178). A risk of conception means a risk of contracting STDs as well. With such a miracle weapon against AIDS – and AIDS, for a long time, has meant certain death at the end of ghastly sufferings – I can’t see many a reasoning mind taking the risk lightly, especially when the horrors of the disease are blasted in your ears daily, year in and year out.

In such a context, what can pornography do for us? I think I know what it can for its producers, but for the viewers it cannot serve the same ‘educative’ purposes as homosexuality (according to Baker) and/or prostitution. At best, it remains theoretical knowledge. At worst, as stressed by sexual ‘educators’ of the past, like Wilhelm Reich, it generates anxiety. Young viewers, especially, might be led to see themselves as inadequately equipped for sex, both physically, with respect to penis size, comparing with the performers’ penises, and psychologically, perceiving that they cannot be callous enough to engage in sexual games.

This is my own interpretation of what Lundberg & Farnham (already quoted in XXVIII) call, with their psychoanalytic lens, an ‘extensive psychological castration of the male.’ It stresses the dismantling of sex-educative institutions for men, and their replacement by a counterproductive substitute.

Incidentally, contrary to common belief, pornography may well be consumed by women. I have already hinted, in my previous essay, at studies cited by Zillmann concerning physiological reactions to erotica. In the current belief, held including by some evolutionary psychologists, such as Gad Saad, holder of a chair on ‘Darwinian consumption’ (sic) at Concordia University (Montreal, Canada), pornography appeals to male psychology, while women are interested in romance novels à la Barbara Cartland (The Consuming Instinct, 2011). No doubt men find no appeal in romance novels, but women’s taste for such books is only one side of the coin. They appeal to a woman as seeker of a long-term partner, seeker of the gentleman who will help her raise her children and who therefore must be faithful, caring, protective, considerate, earn a lot of money, and so on. But remember that the gentleman in question is a springboard for the woman as seeker of gene-providing lovers (springboard model). In this latter state of mind, any reason preventing pornography from appealing to her may be illusory.

In conclusion, the situation, I believe, is like the French saying “Ce sont ceux qui le font le moins qui en parlent le plus” (the less they do it, the more they talk about it), but at the collective level. The fact that “sex is everywhere, from Web to television” (Baker, in his 2006 introduction to SW) is not reassuring, really, even from a non-Puritan point of view. To make it clear from an analogy, the current tendency, in Hollywood movies, to depict heroines as women of action coping with obstacles with their muscles, comes handy. An alien from Mars watching such movies would get a very inaccurate picture of our reality. The motives behind such a distorted picture I can only surmise: on the one hand the need to keep making popular action movies for cash, on the other hand the moral imperative to give women a fair share in our symbolic representations…

But I am no prophet of doom and I bring, instead, a message of hope. Hags can take the place of whores! There is already, I am told, a significant trend in pornography depicting female performers far past the age range usually appealing to men in search of mates (see what these evolutionary determined preferences are in XXVIII). Old women, the refuse of sex life, would be attractive enough to inexperienced men (inexperienced past experiencing age) who badly need training to improve their self-confidence – the training men used to have with prostitutes in more relaxed times. If one of these men can get his hands on such a one, and they are easily available for the prurience never dies, he will give her the time of her life, being like a starved beast of prey, and having developed severe, and interesting, deviations – imaginations. Hence, the refuse gets the best.

Optimizing vs Maximizing

On this topic I will be discussing also a source of Baker & Bellis, namely Despotism and Differential Reproduction. A Darwinian View of History (1986) by Laura Betzig.

My objection was to Baker’s prediction that world population will stabilize in the future (at 11 billion individuals around 2100, a fairly precise prediction). HSC details his arguments. Quoth: “There is a close relationship (a) between family size and life expectancy (P = 0.008, controlled for the geographical areas illustrated) which is not significantly different from the relationship (b) between family size and use of moder contraception (P = 0.004).” (HSC 182, box 7.4). Baker & Bellis here discard modern family planning as having played a motor role in the demographic transition. According to them, contraceptive methods “enhance psychological predispositions and strategies evolved much earlier in mammalian history” (HSC 183), and life expectancy is the key factor. As this factor increases in developing countries, birth rates will diminish, as they have diminished in Western countries with the increase of life expectancy, to stabilize at the number of children that optimizes reproductive success – a number that according to Baker fixes at replacement level, i.e. two children per woman.

This model relies on differential observations about developed and developing countries, rich and poor, and the same observations seem to hold for individuals inside countries: “A first attempt to model the situation was made by Rogers (1990). The conclusions were that at the lower wealth ranges of a population, long-term fitness is maximized by using the currently available wealth to maximize family size. The more wealthy ranges, however, gain relatively little from increasing family size and thus may benefit, in long-term reproductive success, from limiting family size so that those few offspring raised are reproductively more successful. As Rogers recognizes, the conclusions are sensitive to a number of assumptions. At the very least, however, the model shows that the reduction in family size during the demographic transition could well have been a response that actually increased individual reproductive success.” (HSC 183).

Interestingly, these views seem to buttress my own linguistic argument on the etymology of the word ‘proletarian’, an argument I used against Baker’s prediction. My construction of this word derived from Latin proles, i.e. offspring, as meaning those who make many children, is not partaken as such by linguists or Latinists. Generally speaking, the word is construed as meaning those who possess nothing but children, or in the classic Latin-French dictionary by Gaffiot, “qui ne compte dans l’État que par ses enfants” (whose worth in the state depends entirely on his children); but both constructions imply some maximizing reproductive behavior, because if one’s wealth, or worth, equals one’s number of children, then one will maximize one’s number of children, for in the case of wealth or worth a distinction between optimizing and maximizing is irrelevant.

So, both Rogers and I agree that lower classes make more children. However, Darwinian theory, as Betzig explains, predicts that the more wealthy and powerful one is, the more women he will inseminate: “As a rule, the evidence is overwhelming that rich and powerful men do enjoy the greatest degree of polygyny cross culturally” (Betzig, 1986, p. 34), and she quotes Darwin: “Polygamy … is almost universally followed by the leading men in every tribe.” Baker & Bellis, quoting another book by Betzig, write the same, adding some historical restrictions: “the advent of agriculture and animal husbandry (c. 15 000 years ago) seemed to herald a universal swing in the human population towards polygyny and extreme reproductive inequality between males (Betzig, 1988). … The critical factor in this swing seemed to be the clumping of resources associated with agriculture and husbandry and the inevitable increase in differences between males in the resources they could accumulate, defend and offer.” (HSC, 140).

Both sets of data seem hard to reconcile. Why didn’t polygynous men of the past optimize their reproduction and why, instead, did they make more children than proletarians? Had they not a higher life expectancy than the subjected populations? If I had read Betzig before, to be sure, I wouldn’t have written that proletarians have been making more children ‘from the remotest antiquity’ on (XXVIII) without further consideration.

Betzig circumscribes yet another time limit in the validity of her ‘Darwinian view of history’: “A decline in both despotism and differential reproduction seems to coincide with industrialization.” (Betzig, 1986, 97). She hypothesizes that, in a context of technical specialization, a decrease in differential reproduction is a necessary concession from the ruling classes to the useful specialists (p. 104). In the same way that, at the beginning of the twentieth century, some intellectuals warned that Darwinian survival-of-the-fittest mechanisms did not function any longer and there were no more natural checks to the proliferation of defects in industrial societies, which were therefore doomed to see the burden of defective individuals increase, we here have another cesura in our Darwinian view of history across the industrialization line, with differential reproduction reversing from the haves to the have-nots. (Or is it the same idea?)

First of all, the data presented by Betzig might not impair my position as to the behavioral characteristics of proletarians in the remote past as much as one may think, because rich men’s polygyny increases also poor women’s, their servants and others’s philoprogenitiveness, whereas rich women’s reproduction may remain suboptimal.

(As a parenthesis, I would like to expatiate on this point by dismissing a possible objection to my statement in XXVIII that a rich man who cuckolds a poor man contributes to widening the gap between the actual and optimum number of children in that poor family. The objection would be that the poor women having routine sex with their poor partners anyway, children will be born even without a rich man cuckolding the poor man. This is not quite so simple, because a woman is more likely to become pregnant in the course of extra-pair copulation [EPC] than of IPC: “The more fertile the female (i.e. in terms of stage of menstrual cycle and type of contraceptive), the higher the proportion of copulations that are double matings.” [HSC, 198] & “Women are significantly more likely to use contraception during IPCs than during EPCs, particularly double matings.” [ibid.] & “There is a clear increase in the incidence of EPCs, including double-matings, when the risk of conception is greater.” [HSC, 197, box 8-3]. Statistically, my remark must hold true.)

Second, one should perhaps distinguish, even before industrialization, between sex warlords and bourgeoisie. Sex warlords, due to their military way of life, might have had a life expectancy that was hardly higher than their subjects’s. As a result, they too maximized their offspring. Bourgeoisie, on the other hand, is the shrewd and prudent class; they optimize. Baker & Bellis talk about those suboptimal men in sperm competition who are most willing to take a wife as a long-term partner and as a consequence must specialize in parenting skills. What are these parenting skills if not the self-same skills that enable men to provide for the needs of a family in the long run? This is bourgeoisie, biologically speaking.

Finally, even before industrialization, there must have existed in the very social structure checks to extreme reproductive inequalities. Especially in despotic societies, the social pyramid (▲) is the inverted picture of the alleged reproductive pyramid (▼). In the Ottoman Empire, at the passing away of the sultan, one of his numerous children was placed on the throne at the end of shadowy court intrigues (in which women would play a great part) and all his siblings exterminated, so his reproductive success must be regarded as not so very great after all. In Western feudal aristocracies, among which property was indivisible, only the first-born male inherited the land and title. The second-born was destined to become a sterile cleric in the Church, the other ones making a career in the military or disappearing altogether from the scene, in the commonalty. Property being indivisible, feudal interests are disconnected from the number of children; besides the biological urge, there is no social incentive to make many children. Conversely, among classes or under regimes in which conveyances are divided, the interest of the family is clearly to reduce the number of children; dynastic (family) success is impaired by transmission to many siblings.

These several considerations tend to promote the idea that data from primitive tribal societies as regards reproductive inequality ought to be taken with a pinch of salt when discussing other types of societies, civilizations namely, however remote.

I shall now proceed to a few other considerations that the reading of HSC has newly triggered.

Ejaculation

Under the head “Ejaculates” in my previous essay, I described a theoretical model of female mate-guarding I had designed based on a number of assumptions, particularly concerning male ejaculation. The idea was that the volumes ejaculated by a man depend only on time elapsed between ejaculations, and that this allows the woman, in a context of routine sex, to detect, through interoceptive evaluation of the volume ejaculated, unfaithfulness (or cryptic ejaculations outside her). I have found in HSC that such an assumption (volumes depending on time) has been made by biologists too. Baker & Bellis call it the ‘physiological constraint model’: “This model assumes that, at each IPC, males inseminate all of the stored sperm mature enough to be ejaculated. On this model, number of sperm inseminated at each IPC will be a function of time since last ejaculation and the rates at which sperm mature (minus those which are shed or destroyed.” (HSC, 208). They dismiss it, based on laboratory evidence, and propose instead their own ‘topping-up model’, of which I have already talked.

However, another consideration could save my own model, because I have discarded it offhand on a certain misunderstanding and confusion. What the topping-up model is dealing with is the number of sperm ejaculated, not the volume of seminal fluid, and in my own story the important factor is the volume of seminal fluid inseminated in the genital tract, because it is that volume that would be sensed, and evaluated or measured, by an hypothetic interoceptive sense of the woman (not so hypothetic, perhaps, because we will all agree that the genital tract is sensitive; the question is whether its sensitivity would allow the woman to perform the evaluation I surmise).

HSC confirms that the volumes of seminal fluid and the volumes of sperm are two different stories: “In principle, a female could also gain from stimulating her partner to ejaculate without copulation in order to observe the amount of seminal fluid ejaculated by the male. This could give some information on how long it is since last ejaculated. However, as seminal fluids recover relatively quickly (Mann and Lutwak-Mann, 1981), the female could probably only tell whether the male had ejaculated in the previous 12 hours or so. Within the context of her partner’s infidelity, however, this could still be useful information.” (HSC, 115) Baker & Bellis come to the same idea of female mate-guarding through information got from the amount of seminal fluid ejaculated, but they apparently do not think such estimates possible inside the female genital tract: the information has to be gathered from ‘ejaculates without copulation’, be it through masturbation or fellatio. This being said, they explain how such information from seminal fluid works, and what kind of assumptions it allows.

Perhaps the data could be further refined, and correspondences established between volumes of ejaculated seminal fluid and sperm, to see if any correlations exist (if such studies exist, I pray the reader to forgive me for being a layman.) Let us assume for a moment a strong correlation between the amounts of both elements, seminal fluid and sperm, during ejaculation (although we’ve just seen the story is different for each). That would allow my model to stand on its feet, beside the topping-up model, with only one further restriction. If the volumes ejaculated depend on (1) time elapsed since last ejaculation and (2) time spent together by the partners (topping-up model), the woman could still detect the man’s infidelity via estimates of the volumes he ejaculates in her tract, thanks to an hypothetic interoceptive sense, if the partners have regular routine sex and if at the same time they have adopted a regular, routinized way of life by which they spend the same amount of time together from one week to the other. Such conditions being fulfilled, any variation of the volumes would warn the woman that something is afoot. A process of extreme routinization in every aspect of life is implied in successful mate-guarding.

Male Opportunism

Under the head “Male Masturbation,” I expatiated on some views I had published elsewhere, the gist of which was that the young man refraining from the practice would be sending signals to women that he is sexually ‘on’. “So what?” a biologist might reply, “Don’t you know that males are urgent and females coy (HSC, 13, box 2.7)? Even if the woman gets signals, being coy she can’t make nothing of it. A male sending signals, that makes no sense; the man just takes action.” It is true that such views of mine at first sight do not quite fit the urgent-coy dichotomy, nor the more popular one of active-passive. To my mind, the male is opportunist: not so much active as ‘activated’. Truly active men are sexual predators and rapists; the bulk of us is not in search of preys but of opportunities. In the absence of certain signals, the man remains passive. I contend he can force the woman to send signals to him, by pleasing her. The idea of opportunism is of course implied in male urgency, but it qualifies it. Unqualified urgency is predation.

Another way to get at the idea of opportunism is, indirectly, through the notion of coquettishness and of a coquette. The word has fallen into desuetude, but Henry James’s stories and novels, for instance, give us a clue as to its importance in not so remote a past. A coquette was not a fallen woman yet, but she could not be regarded as a lady any more. In a nutshell, the coquette would send deceptive signals to opportunist men, she would ‘activate’ them for the mere fun of it, and that was a disgrace.

A man who gets signalled at by women everywhere he goes is what I shall call, for the sake of simplicity, an alpha male. Beta or zeta males often enough admit they suffer from woman’s choosiness (a consequence of her coyness), but they know what an alpha male is; when they spot one, they do their best to become one of his close acquaintances. It’s the best way they can find to get access to women, because an alpha male is bound to create much disappointment among the feminine crowds that signal at him madly (there is just not enough time in a man’s life to enable him to lavish his assiduities in all directions whence the signals come), and, either by despair or resentment, many broken hearts will let the zeta boys bring them a much-needed solace. It’s the well-known story of Elvis’s hairdresser and that of the inconspicuous bassist of the Rolling Stones. (I hope these examples will not appear too trivial. I know many a savant book on the market proffers abundant trivialities, but I have always thought they come from the editors of the publishing house’s staffs, rather than from the authors themselves.)

Penis Size

But let us return to our favorite subject, on which Baker & Bellis provide us with new insights.

Quoth: “when the lineage leading to the genus Homo began to evolve large brains and hence large vaginas, selection was imposed, via sperm competition, on males with larger penises.” (HSC, 174). Here I perceive some circularity in the reasoning. Baker & Bellis say that large penises are better able to remove alien sperm from large vaginas. As we have seen under the head “Female Orgasm” at the beginning of this essay, a large penis is a significant advantage only in the context of rampant promiscuity, for we have expressed some doubt on the possibility that the penis be able to remove sperm stored in the cervix (although Baker & Bellis say it ‘perhaps’ can). If it cannot remove cervical sperm, its action is limited to flowback sperm, so-called, that is sperm forming a seminal pool in the upper vagina, after insemination and before flowback. Which means, its utility is limited to cases of intercourse occurring shortly after another intercourse has taken place with the same female. Thus, a significant selective pressure towards large penises could not exist outside rampant promiscuity (perhaps circumscribed to limited mating seasons). But rampant promiscuity, like among chimpanzees, goes with large penises. Chimpanzees have the highest penis size to body size ratio among the principal primate species; are their brains particularly large ? 275-500 cm3, compared with small-penis gorillas: 340-752 cm3, prlease find the brain size to body ratio for both, and tell me which species has the greatest. If chimpanzees do not have large brains, large brains are not causative in any sense among them.

Another insight I would like to discuss under the present head: “If penis size is an important factor in sperm competition, it would be surprising if males and females did not have some reaction to penis size. First, males should perceive males with a penis larger than themselves as more of a threat if they ever show a sexual interest in the same woman. Second, females should prefer to mate with males who will give them male descendants with a penis more efficient at removing a rival’s sperm.” (HSC, 174).

It has been remarked (in German völkisch circles), based on the evidence of Greek statues, that small-penis men have been selected against inside Caucasoid populations. It would not be a waste of time to collect penis measurements on an appropriate sample of Greek statues, treat them with tables of correspondence or a formula converting penis size at rest into size during erection, and then compare the results with the data provided by HSC on contemporary penis sizes: for Caucasoids 14-15 cm on average (HSC, 169, box 6.12, from Rushton & Bogaert, 1987). (Incidentally, I remember that, in high school and college, a persistent rumor was that the average size of an erect penis was 18 cm. The adverse effects of such an evil rumor on the self-confidence of inexperienced young men are easy to imagine. The psychologic warfare waged in the field of sex notions is endless. Another fiendish rumor construed testicular asymmetry, the normal case, as an abnormality that required chirurgical intervention.) No doubt the results of such a study would confirm that small-penis men have been selected against from antiquity to modern days.

One cannot rule out, of course, some artistic convention. Ithyphallic satyrs, for instance, are represented with huge penises. The convention would then reflect the notion of a trade-off: testosteronized hormotypes are beastlike unspiritual beings. One could also contend that, as most of these statues were orders from the upper classes, from priests for temples, from wealthy individuals for private altars and esthetic enjoyment, and from rulers for publicity, they reflect these classes’ hormotypes. That is, Greek upper classes were not particularly testosteronized. Which leads to the incident question as to how testosterone is distributed in society. Given the manner in which I describe the bourgeoisie, above, I am not expecting that upper classes be highly testosteronized as a rule.

Sexual Indifference?

Another of my previous contentions I would like to discuss further. I talked about a possible sexual indifference arising with time from restraint, but as I did not expatiate on what I meant, some may find the statement bold and oppose me with the medical evidence that shows that on the contrary sexual restraint provokes perversions and other forms of mental trouble.

I always found baffling the idea that Puritans, who are married men, should be deemed better examples of moral ‘self-conquest’ than Catholic clerics, who, normally, are sexually abstinent. Max Weber, for instance, calls Puritans “virtuosi of asceticism,” as if it were more ascetic to live monogamously with one wife than to abstain from sex altogether. The conclusion I have drawn from the ubiquity of such a judgment, if this judgment be unprejudiced (to be sure, it is absent from such a profound book as The Varieties of Religious Experience by William James), is that it is more difficult not to be a lecher when having sex routinely than to remain consistent and firm in one’s abstinence, and that it must be because over time abstinence creates an indifference to sex – rather than perverted tastes – becoming a habit, maybe not too unpleasant nor too uncomfortable, and thus not so praiseworthy as the resisting temptation of extra-pair intercourse by a married man engaged in routine sex year in and year out. Even more so if abstinence leads to impotence in the long run, because then a eunuch has no merit at all abstaining from sex. It is perhaps more difficult also for the routine-sex man to refrain from consuming alcoholic drinks and other intoxicants, from seeking base entertainments and other things associated with a worldly unascetic life, from anger, envy, resentment, whereas overriding these would be a mere trifle for the no-sex man (qui peut le plus peut le moins) and not so meritorious as a consequence. – Unless the whole affair is a misunderstanding on my part, and in the above statement by Weber is implied, rather, that Puritans have succeeded in their ideal of monogamy whereas the Catholic clergy has failed in his own ideal of sexual abstinence, be it through masturbation, and thus has always been a community of failures and frauds.

The Pill

From the quotes HSC 197 and 198 above, it must be clear that a woman taking the pill is less likely, all other things being equal, to cuckold her partner, because a woman normally cuckolds her partner during the fertile phases of her cycle. So much so for the sexual adventurism of contemporary women.

Paternity Tests

In Sex in the Future, published in 1999, Baker lays great hopes on the paternity test technology; his visions of the future are grounded on the basic idea that the technology will become widespread. Fifteen years later, why are paternity tests not a common feature yet? Why have smartphones become in a few years, or even months, a staple of the Western world, and not paternity tests? Why such inertia? The market exists; over the last couple of years, there has been 3.9 million births each year in the US alone, 10 700 births per day.

The answer is that free access is not enough. The state must make tests compulsory for each birth. Otherwise, the technology will never spread, it will remain restricted to litigation as it is today and has always been since it has become available. Why, if the man asks his partner to take a test, she will be disgusted by his suspicion, or terrified at the idea of being exposed, and she will miscarry. No man can ask for a test in free-market conditions. I suppose no man has ever asked for it.

Consequences of a generalization would be far-reaching indeed, notably in one direction untold by Baker. The polygynous is a kind of parasite of the monogynous. The monogynous can (and had rather) live without the polygynous, whereas the polygynous needs the monogynous in order to cuckold  him behind his back. No doubt, often enough crop up in the monogynous’ mind fantasies of uprooting. Is he to blame for that? No more than the polygynous for his cuckolding. With paternity tests generalized, the wheat would be separated from the chaff – in this world.

Mutations

“It is a mathematical inevitability that populations come to be dominated by those heritable characteristics that impart greatest multiplication power to the descendants of the lineage founder.” (HSC, 7, box 2.2). This is the fundamental of ‘behavioral ecology’ and what allows her to speak of reproductive ‘success’ and ‘failure’. To complete it, “Thus, when we come to examine the sexual behaviour of humans or other animals at the present time, we are seeing populations that are dominated numerically by heritable characteristics that imparted the greatest multiplication power on generations of past possessors. This statement has the certainty of all mathematical axioms and as such is immune to any further philosophical or ideological discussion.” (ibid.) I certainly do not wish to discuss a mathematical axiom, but in case it would serve as a call to “multiply and replenish the earth,” that is as a moral rule of conduct, I may have some objections to present on philosophical grounds.

As Oscar Wilde said, “The only thing one really knows about human nature is that it changes. Change is the one quality we can predicate of it. The systems that fail are those that rely on the permanence of human nature, and not on its growth and development.” (The Soul of Man Under Socialism). At the root of change in living forms, we find mutations, so the future belongs to mutants. If the future belongs to mutants, it doesn’t matter in the least whose offspring it is that mutates. The mutant of the future does not look more like his ancestor than like any sterile individual of our days.

When a mutation procures a sustainable advantage and creates a mutant species, it is not the qualities my descent and I do share that are important to my descent, but those they and I do not share. Were my descent not my descent, but another’s, it would be the same; my mutant descent and I are strangers to each other, in virtue of that very minority rule that is at the ground of inclusive fitness or kin selection: “Any two members of a species, whether they belong to the same family or not, usually share more than 90 per cent of their genes. What, then, are we talking about when we speak of the relatedness between brothers as ½, or between first cousins as 1/8? The answer is that brothers share ½ of their genes over and above the 90 per cent (or whatever it is) that all individuals share in any case.” (Richard Dawkins, The Selfish Gene, 30th Anniversary Edition, p. 288). If the genes I share with a few are of more paramount importance to me than the genes I share with many, then the genes I am the only one to possess are the top of the top, and the rest is so much rubbish. Thus could speak the mutant’s body.

By the way, remember what I said about those hopeless low-status women, who would maximize their offspring in any case because they can expect nothing but a miracle. Here the miracle is the mutation. If we aim at giving birth to the founder of the mutant lineage of the future, then we must maximize the number of our children. Away with optimizing!

Technology vs Biology

Biologists occasionally report the attacks they are subjected to, because of their writings, by mystics and philosophers, but they fail to see, seemingly, that their most dangerous enemy is not those metaphysicians and literati, but technology – not because technology would prove biologists wrong, but because it is going to make their knowledge unimportant, at best anecdotal, when intelligence becomes independent of any genetic support.

No doubt biologists can explain technological developments in Darwinian terms, and I would be delighted to read such treatises, but one cannot help smiling when reading phrases such as “if the recent … technological environment stays stable long enough” (HSC, 186), for this ‘long enough’ must indeed be a long time, the authors dealing with evolutionary scales. The phrase is naive, and it was already a little bit naive in 1995. In 1997 the computer Deep Blue beat the world champion at chess; today no human chess master can beat a computer. Exponential trends in the development of computing and other technologies have led some scholars to forecast a ‘singularity’ in the future, although I strongly object to the name because it compares something that has never happened yet under the conditions of our experience, namely an intelligence independent from genetic support, with things that cannot happen under no condition of our experience, namely infinite density in relativistic black holes and infinite heat in the relativistic Big Bang, so-called singularities of physics (see Thoughts III here).

Elsewhere (here, in French) I have stressed that genetic reproduction is a hindrance to knowledge transmission, because every new individual must be taught from scratch, and the loss of time and energy this state of affairs generates is tremendous. This, linked with certain characteristics of mental activity, has convinced me of an autonomous movement of technology towards the making of a new kind of being. Let me add the following. By responding to needs, technology has made the biological mechanisms that respond to those needs an encumbrance. It creates the need to get rid of these biological mechanisms, even though they are connected to the recipient organs of the service. In contemporary urban settings, people are compelled to devote significant portions of their time to futile physical exercizes, such as jogging on treadmills, with the sole aim of preventing their bodies from impairing their activity. Our bodies are not suited any more to the life we’re living.

To illustrate the autonomy of technological development, let’s take leisure. Technological conditions have been fulfilled for decades to put an end to most of human toil, but humanity keeps toiling. “Leisure is a condition for which the human species has been badly prepared, because until very recently it was enjoyed by only a few, who contributed very little to the gene pool.” (B. F. Skinner, Beyond Freedom and Dignity).

Only a collapse of the technological civilization could preserve genetic transmission. By reading Baker’s writings, one is primed, in a way, to see any achievement outside reproduction as castles in the air (however transient the priming may be and the final impression always that science must go on). This, in Ibsen’s famous play The Master Builder, is of what Hilde convinces the master builder Solness – he dies before eloping with her, by the way. Technology, however, is no castle in the air if its definition is: the making of a new being. DER GEIST is awakening.

January 3rd, 2016